A formal theory, T, is defined when the following conditions are satisfied:
1. | A countable set of symbols. A finite string of symbols is called an expression of T. |
2. | There is a subset of the expressions called the set of well-formed formulas (wffs) of T. |
3. | A set of well-formed formulas is set aside and called the set of axioms of T. |
4. | There is a finite set of relations among well-formed formulas, called rules of inference. |
Deduction or Proof in formal theory T
A deduction (or proof) in formal theory T is a sequence of well-formed formulas such that for each well-formed formula in the sequence either it is an axiom of or it is a direct consequence of some of the preceding well-formed formulas using the rules of inference.
More formally, a deduction in T is a sequence of well-formed formulas
A1, A2, ..., An
such that, for each i,
either 1. Ai is an axiom of T.
or 2. Ai is a direct consequence of the preceding well-formed formulas using the rules of inference.
Theorem of formal theory T
A theorem of is a well-formed formula A (say) such that there is a deduction the last well-formed formula of which is A. In other words, there is a sequence of well-formed formulas, as defined in the definition of proof, of which the last last well-formed formula is A. Such a deduction (or proof) is called deduction of A (or proof of A.)
More formally, we say A is a theorem of the formal theory T if, and only if, there is a deduction (i.e. proof)
A1, A2, ..., An
such that An is A. The notation
A
means that A is a theorem of T.
From the above formalization, we see that a proof in the formal theory T is a deduction starting from the axioms. In other words, it starts from the set whose members are axioms of T . And this means we shall need also the more general notion of deduction from some given set of well-formed formulas.
Consequence in formal theory T
Let Γ be a set of well-formed formulas in T. A well-formed formula A is said to be a consequence of a set Γ if, and only if, there is a sequence of well-formed formulas
A1, A2, ..., An
such that An = A and , for each i, 1 ≤ i ≤ n, one of the following holds:
a. | Ai is an axiom or |
b. | Ai is in Γ or |
c. | Ai is a direct consequence by some rule of inference of some of the preceding well-formed formulas in the sequence. |
Such a sequence is called a proof (or deduction) of A from the set of well-formed formulas Γ. The member of Γ are called the hypothesis or premisses of the proof. In other words, well-formed formulas in the set Γ are called the hypothesis or premisses of the proof. And
Γ A
is an abbreviation for "A is a consequences of Γ" or "A is deducible from Γ."
If Γ is a finite set [of well-formed formulas] {B1, B2, ..., Bn}, we write
{B1, B2, ..., Bn} A
or simply
B1, B2, ..., Bn A
On the other hand, a theorem of Γ is deducible from the empty set of well-formed formulas. In other words, a theorem A is a consequence of an empty set [of well-formed formulas].
Formally,
If a set of well-formed formulas Γ in is the empty set {} or 0, then 0 A if, and only if, A is a theorem.
Note that it is customary to omit the sign '0' and simply write
A
See the definition of theorem above.
Properties of the Consequence
The following are properties of the notion of consequence.
Proposition 1. | If Γ ⊆ Δ and Γ
A,
then Δ
A.
This proposition asserts that if A is provable from a set Γ of hypotheses, then, if we add still more hypothesis, A is still provable. |
Proposition 2. | Γ
A if, and only if, there is a
finite subset Δ of Γ such that Δ
A.
Note that "one direction" is follows from Assertion 1. The other direction is obvious when we notice that any proof of A from Γ uses only a finite number of hypotheses from Γ. |
Proposition 3. | If Δ
A, and, for each B
in Δ, Γ
B, then Γ
A.
This proposition asserts that if A is provable from hypotheses in Δ, and each hypothesis in Δ is provable from the hypotheses in Γ, then A is provable from hypotheses in Γ. |